forked from idris-hackers/software-foundations
-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 0
/
Copy pathTactics.lidr
1165 lines (821 loc) · 39.9 KB
/
Tactics.lidr
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
= Tactics : More Basic Tactics
This chapter introduces several additional proof strategies and tactics that
allow us to begin proving more interesting properties of functional programs. We
will see:
- how to use auxiliary lemmas in both "forward-style" and "backward-style"
proofs;
- how to reason about data constructors (in particular, how to use the fact
that they are injective and disjoint);
- how to strengthen an induction hypothesis (and when such strengthening is
required); and
- more details on how to reason by case analysis.
> module Tactics
>
> import Basics
> import Induction
> import Pruviloj
>
> %access public export
>
> %default total
>
> %language ElabReflection
>
== The \idr{exact} Tactic
We often encounter situations where the goal to be proved is _exactly_ the same
as some hypothesis in the context or some previously proved lemma.
> silly1 : (n, m, o, p : Nat) -> (n = m) -> [n,o] = [n,p] -> [n,o] = [m,p]
Here, we could prove this with rewrites:
> silly1 n m o p eq1 eq2 = rewrite eq2 in
> rewrite eq1 in Refl
or the dependent pattern matching:
```idris
silly1 n n o o Refl Refl = Refl
```
\todo[inline]{Write more about dependent pattern matching techinque. Maybe move
to an earlier chapter?}
as we have done several times before. We can achieve the same effect by a series
of tactic applications, using \idr{exact} instead of the
\idr{rewrite}+\idr{Refl} combination:
\todo[inline]{Explain \idr{intros} (move text from `Basics`?), \idr{Var} and
\idr{rewriteWith}. Explain the "backwards" order.}
\todo[inline]{\idr{| _ => fail []} is needed for totality}
> silly1' : (n, m, o, p : Nat) -> (n = m) -> [n,o] = [n,p] -> [n,o] = [m,p]
> silly1' = %runElab silly1_tac
> where
> silly1_tac : Elab ()
> silly1_tac = do
> [n,m,o,p,eq1,eq2] <- intros
> | _ => fail []
> rewriteWith $ Var eq1
> exact $ Var eq2
(This tactic is called `apply` in Coq.)
\todo[inline]{The following doesn't seem to hold in Idris, you have to manually
apply things with \idr{RApp} for \idr{exact} to work. Maybe there's another
tactic?}
The \idr{exact} tactic also works with _conditional_ hypotheses and lemmas: if the
statement being applied is an implication, then the premises of this implication
will be added to the list of subgoals needing to be proved.
> silly2 : (n, m, o, p : Nat) -> (n = m) ->
> ((q, r : Nat) -> q = r -> [q,o] = [r,p]) ->
> [n,o] = [m,p]
> silly2 = %runElab silly2_tac
> where
> silly2_tac : Elab ()
> silly2_tac = do
> [n,m,o,p,eq1,eq2] <- intros
> | _ => fail []
> exact $ (((Var eq2) `RApp` (Var n)) `RApp` (Var m)) `RApp` (Var eq1)
You may find it instructive to experiment with this proof and see if there is a
way to complete it using just \idr{rewrite} instead of \idr{exact}.
\todo[inline]{Edit}
Typically, when we use \idr{exact h}, the statement \idr{h} will begin with a
`(...)` that binds some _universal variables_. When Idris matches the current
goal against the conclusion of \idr{h}, it will try to find appropriate values
for these variables. For example, when we do \idr{exact $ Var eq2} in the
following proof, the universal variable \idr{q} in \idr{eq2} gets instantiated
with \idr{n} and \idr{r} gets instantiated with \idr{m}.
> silly2a : (n, m : Nat) -> (n,n) = (m,m) ->
> ((q, r : Nat) -> (q,q) = (r,r) -> [q] = [r]) ->
> [n] = [m]
> silly2a = %runElab silly2a_tac
> where
> silly2a_tac : Elab ()
> silly2a_tac = do
> [n,m,eq1,eq2] <- intros
> | _ => fail []
> exact $ (((Var eq2) `RApp` (Var n)) `RApp` (Var m)) `RApp` (Var eq1)
==== Exercise: 2 stars, optional (silly_ex)
Complete the following proof without using `simpl`.
> silly_ex : ((n : Nat) -> evenb n = True -> oddb (S n) = True)
> -> evenb 3 = True -> oddb 4 = True
> silly_ex = ?remove_me -- %runElab silly_ex_tac
> where
> silly_ex_tac : Elab ()
> silly_ex_tac = ?silly_ex_tac_rhs
$\square$
To use the \idr{exact} tactic, the (conclusion of the) fact being applied must
match the goal exactly -- for example, \idr{exact} will not work if the left and
right sides of the equality are swapped.
> silly3_firsttry : (n : Nat) -> True = n == 5 ->
> (S (S n)) == 7 = True
> silly3_firsttry = %runElab silly3_firsttry_tac
> where
> silly3_firsttry_tac : Elab ()
> silly3_firsttry_tac = do
> [_,h] <- intros
> | _ => fail []
Here we cannot use \idr{exact} directly, but we can use the \idr{symmetry}
tactic, which switches the left and right sides of an equality in the goal.
> symmetry
> exact $ Var h
==== Exercise: 3 stars (apply_exercise1)
(_Hint_: You can use \idr{exact} with previously defined lemmas, not just
hypotheses in the context. Remember that `:search` is your friend.)
> rev : (l : List x) -> List x
> rev [] = []
> rev (h::t) = (rev t) ++ [h]
> rev_exercise1 : (l, l' : List Nat) -> l = rev l' -> l' = rev l
> rev_exercise1 = ?remove_me1 -- %runElab rev_exercise1_tac
> where
> rev_exercise1_tac : Elab ()
> rev_exercise1_tac = ?rev_exercise1_tac_rhs
$\square$
==== Exercise: 1 star, optional (apply_rewrite)
Briefly explain the difference between the tactics \idr{exact} and
\idr{rewriteWith}. What are the situations where both can usefully be applied?
> -- FILL IN HERE
$\square$
== The \idr{apply} Tactic
The following silly example uses two rewrites in a row to get from `[a,b]` to
`[e,f]`.
> trans_eq_example : (a, b, c, d, e, f : Nat) ->
> [a,b] = [c,d] -> [c,d] = [e,f] -> [a,b] = [e,f]
> trans_eq_example a b c d e f eq1 eq2 = rewrite eq1 in
> rewrite eq2 in Refl
Note that this can also be proven with dependent pattern matching:
```idris
trans_eq_example a b a b a b Refl Refl = Refl
```
Since this is a common pattern, we might like to pull it out as a lemma
recording, once and for all, the fact that equality is transitive.
> trans_eq : (n, m, o : x) -> n = m -> m = o -> n = o
> trans_eq n n n Refl Refl = Refl
(This lemma already exists in Idris' stdlib under the name of \idr{trans}.)
Now, we should be able to use \idr{trans_eq} to prove the above example.
However, to do this we need a slight refinement of the \idr{exact} tactic.
> trans_eq_example' : (a, b, c, d, e, f : Nat) ->
> [a,b] = [c,d] -> [c,d] = [e,f] -> [a,b] = [e,f]
> trans_eq_example' = %runElab trans_eq_example_tac
> where
> trans_eq_example_tac : Elab ()
> trans_eq_example_tac = do
> [a,b,c,d,e,f,eq1,eq2] <- intros
> | _ => fail []
\todo[inline]{Edit: Idris apparently can figure things out itself via
\idr{solve}. Explain the quotation syntax.}
If we simply tell Idris \idr{apply (Var `{trans_eq}) ..} at this point, it can
tell (by matching the goal against the conclusion of the lemma) that it should
instantiate \idr{x} with \idr{[Nat]}, \idr{n} with \idr{[a,b]}, and \idr{o} with
\idr{[e,f]}. However, the matching process doesn't determine an instantiation
for \idr{m}: we have to supply one explicitly by adding with (m:=[c,d]) to the
invocation of \idr{apply}.
> [_,_,_,_,_,_] <- apply (Var `{trans_eq})
> [True, True, True, True, False, False]
> | _ => fail []
> solve
> exact $ Var eq1
> exact $ Var eq2
==== Exercise: 3 stars, optional (apply_with_exercise)
> trans_eq_exercise : (n, m, o, p : Nat) ->
> m = (minusTwo o) ->
> (n + p) = m ->
> (n + p) = (minusTwo o)
> trans_eq_exercise = ?remove_me2 -- %runElab trans_eq_exercise_tac
> where
> trans_eq_exercise_tac : Elab ()
> trans_eq_exercise_tac = ?trans_eq_exercise_rhs
$\square$
== The \idr{inversion} Tactic
Recall the definition of natural numbers:
```idris
data Nat : Type where
Z : Nat
S : Nat -> Nat
```
It is obvious from this definition that every number has one of two forms:
either it is the constructor \idr{Z} or it is built by applying the constructor
\idr{S} to another number. But there is more here than meets the eye: implicit
in the definition (and in our informal understanding of how datatype
declarations work in other programming languages) are two more facts:
- The constructor \idr{S} is _injective_. That is, if \idr{S n = S m}, it must
be the case that \idr{n = m}.
- The constructors \idr{Z} and \idr{S} are _disjoint_. That is, \idr{Z} is not
equal to \idr{S n} for any \idr{n}.
Similar principles apply to all inductively defined types: all constructors are
injective, and the values built from distinct constructors are never equal. For
lists, the \idr{(::)} constructor is injective and \idr{Nil} is different from
every non-empty list. For booleans, \idr{True} and \idr{False} are different.
(Since neither \idr{True} nor \idr{False} take any arguments, their injectivity
is not interesting.) And so on.
Idris provides a tactic called \idr{injective} that allows us to exploit these
principles in proofs. To see how to use it, let's show explicitly that the
\idr{S} constructor is injective:
> S_injective : (n, m : Nat) -> S n = S m -> n = m
> S_injective = %runElab S_injective_tac
> where
> covering
> S_injective_tac : Elab ()
> S_injective_tac = do
> [n, m, h] <- intros
> | _ => fail []
By writing \idr{injective (Var h) res} at this point, we are asking Idris to
generate all equations that it can infer from \idr{h} as additional hypotheses,
replacing variables in the goal as it goes. In the present example, this amounts
to adding a new hypothesis \idr{h1 : n = m} and replacing \idr{n} by \idr{m} in
the goal.
\todo[inline]{Explain \idr{gensym}, \idr{unproduct} and \idr{hypothesis}}
> res <- gensym "sInj"
> injective (Var h) res
> unproduct (Var res)
> hypothesis
Here's a more interesting example that shows how multiple equations can be
derived at once.
\todo[inline]{Works quite fast in Elab shell but hangs the compiler}
> -- inversion_ex1 : (n, m, o : Nat) -> [n, m] = [o, o] -> [n] = [m]
> -- inversion_ex1 = %runElab inversion_ex1_tac
> -- where
> -- inversion_ex1_tac : Elab ()
> -- inversion_ex1_tac = do
> -- [n, m, o, eq] <- intros
> -- | _ => fail []
> -- eqinj <- gensym "eqinj"
> -- injective (Var eq) eqinj
> --
> -- eqinj2 <- gensym "eqinj2" -- manual destructuring
> -- both (Var eqinj) !(gensym "natnat") eqinj2
> -- neqo <- gensym "neqo"
> -- eqinj3 <- gensym "eqinj3"
> -- both (Var eqinj2) no eqinj3
> -- meqos <- gensym "meqos"
> -- both (Var eqinj3) mos !(gensym "uu")
> --
> -- oeqn <- gensym "oeqn"
> -- symmetryAs (Var neqo) oeqn
> -- symmetry
> -- rewriteWith $ Var oeqn
> -- exact $ Var meqos
> -- solve
Note that we need to pass the parameter \idr{eqinj} which will be bound to
equations that \idr{injective} generates.
\todo[inline]{Remove when a release with
https://github.com/idris-lang/Idris-dev/pull/3925 happens}
==== Exercise: 1 star (inversion_ex3)
> inversion_ex3 : (x, y, z : a) -> (l, j : List a) ->
> x :: y :: l = z :: j ->
> y :: l = x :: j ->
> x = y
> inversion_ex3 = ?remove_me3 -- %runElab inversion_ex3_tac
> where
> inversion_ex3_tac : Elab ()
> inversion_ex3_tac = ?inversion_ex3_tac_rhs
$\square$
\todo[inline]{Edit}
When used on a hypothesis involving an equality between _different_ constructors
(e.g., \idr{S n = Z}), \idr{injective} solves the goal immediately. Consider the
following proof:
> beq_nat_0_l : Z == n = True -> n = Z
We can proceed by case analysis on n. The first case is trivial.
> beq_nat_0_l {n=Z} _ = Refl
However, the second one doesn't look so simple: assuming \idr{0 == S n' = True},
we must show \idr{S n' = 0}, but the latter clearly contradictory! The way
forward lies in the assumption. After simplifying the goal state, we see that
\idr{0 == S n' = True} has become \idr{False = True}:
\todo[inline]{How to show impossible cases from Elab?}
> beq_nat_0_l {n=(S _)} prf = absurd prf
If we use \idr{absurd} on this hypothesis, Idris allows us to safely infer any
conclusion from it, in this case our goal of \idr{n = 0}.
This is an instance of a logical principle known as the principle of explosion,
which asserts that a contradictory hypothesis entails anything, even false
things!
> inversion_ex4 : (n : Nat) -> S n = Z -> 2 + 2 = 5
> -- we need "sym" because Prelude.Nat only disproves "Z = S n" for us
> inversion_ex4 n prf = absurd $ sym prf
In simple cases like this, we could've also solved this with matching on
\idr{prf}:
```idris
inversion_ex4 _ Refl impossible
```
> inversion_ex5 : (n, m : Nat) -> False = True -> [n] = [m]
> inversion_ex5 n m prf = absurd prf
Again, here we can also write
```idris
inversion_ex5 _ _ Refl impossible
```
If you find the principle of explosion confusing, remember that these proofs are
not actually showing that the conclusion of the statement holds. Rather, they
are arguing that, if the nonsensical situation described by the premise did
somehow arise, then the nonsensical conclusion would follow. We'll explore the
principle of explosion of more detail in the next chapter.
==== Exercise: 1 star (inversion_ex6)
> inversion_ex6 : (x, y, z : a) -> (l, j : List a) ->
> x :: y :: l = [] ->
> y :: l = z :: j ->
> x = z
> inversion_ex6 x y z l j prf prf1 = ?inversion_ex6_rhs
$\square$
To summarize this discussion, suppose \idr{h} is a hypothesis in the context
or a previously proven lemma of the form
\idr{c a1 a2 ... an = d b1 b2 ... bm}
\todo[inline]{Edit, especially the \idr{disjoint} part}
for some constructors \idr{c} and \idr{d} and arguments \idr{a1 ... an} and
\idr{b1 ... bm}. Then \idr{injective h} and \idr{disjoint h} have the following
effects:
- If \idr{c} and \idr{d} are the same constructor, then, by the injectivity of
this constructor, we know that \idr{a1 = b1}, \idr{a2 = b2}, etc. The
\idr{injective h} adds these facts to the context and tries to use them to
rewrite the goal.
- If \idr{c} and \idr{d} are different constructors, then the hypothesis
\idr{h} is contradictory, and the current goal doesn't have to be considered
at all. In this case, \idr{disjoint h} marks the current goal as completed
and pops it off the goal stack.
The injectivity of constructors allows us to reason that \idr{(n, m : Nat) -> S
n = S m -> n = m}. The converse of this implication is an instance of a more
general fact about both constructors and functions, which we will find useful in
a few places below:
> f_equal : (f : a -> b) -> (x, y : a) -> x = y -> f x = f y
> f_equal f x x Refl = Refl
(This is called \idr{cong} in Idris' stdlib.)
== Using Tactics on Hypotheses
\todo[inline]{Edit, Idris runs \idr{compute} on hypotheses automatically}
By default, most tactics work on the goal formula and leave the context
unchanged. However, most tactics also have a variant that performs a similar
operation on a statement in the context. For example, the tactic \idr{compute}
in H performs simplification in the hypothesis named \idr{h} in the context.
> S_inj : (n, m : Nat) -> (b : Bool) ->
> S n == S m = b -> n == m = b
> S_inj = %runElab S_inj_tac
> where
> S_inj_tac : Elab ()
> S_inj_tac = do
> [n, m, b, eq] <- intros
> | _ => fail []
> exact $ Var eq
\todo[inline]{Edit}
Similarly, \idr{applyIn l h} matches some conditional statement \idr{l} (of the
form \idr{l1 -> l2}, say) against a hypothesis \idr{h} in the context. However,
unlike ordinary \idr{exact} (which rewrites a goal matching \idr{l2} into a
subgoal \idr{l1}), \idr{applyIn l h n} matches \idr{h} against \idr{l1} and, if
successful, binds the result \idr{l2} to \idr{n}.
In other words, \idr{applyIn l h} gives us a form of "forward reasoning": from
\idr{l1 -> l2} and a hypothesis matching \idr{l1}, it produces a hypothesis
matching \idr{l2}. By contrast, \idr{exact l} is "backward reasoning": it says
that if we know \idr{l1->l2} and we are trying to prove \idr{l2}, it suffices to
prove \idr{l1}.
Here is a variant of a proof from above, using forward reasoning throughout
instead of backward reasoning.
> silly3' : (n, m : Nat) -> (n == 5 = True -> m == 7 = True) ->
> True = n == 5 -> True = m == 7
> silly3' = %runElab silly3_tac
> where
> silly3_tac : Elab ()
> silly3_tac = do
> [n,m,eq,h] <- intros
> | _ => fail []
> hsym <- symmetryAs (Var h) "hsym"
> happ <- applyAs (Var eq) (Var hsym) "happ"
> happsym <- symmetryAs (Var happ) "happsym"
> exact $ Var happsym
Forward reasoning starts from what is _given_ (premises, previously proven
theorems) and iteratively draws conclusions from them until the goal is reached.
Backward reasoning starts from the _goal_, and iteratively reasons about what
would imply the goal, until premises or previously proven theorems are reached.
If you've seen informal proofs before (for example, in a math or computer
science class), they probably used forward reasoning. In general, idiomatic use
of Idris elab scripts tends to favor backward reasoning, but in some situations
the forward style can be easier to think about.
==== Exercise: 3 stars, recommended (plus_n_n_injective)
Practice using "in" variants in this exercise. (Hint: use \idr{plus_n_Sm}.)
> plus_n_n_injective : n + n = m + m -> n = m
> plus_n_n_injective = ?plus_n_n_injective_rhs
$\square$
== Varying the Induction Hypothesis
Sometimes it is important to control the exact form of the induction hypothesis
when carrying out inductive proofs in Idris elab script. In particular, we need
to be careful about which of the assumptions we move (using \idr{intros}) from
the goal to the context before invoking the \idr{induction} tactic. For example,
suppose we want to show that the \idr{double} function is injective -- i.e., that
it maps different arguments to different results:
> double_injective : double n = double m -> n = m
> double_injective {n=Z} {m=Z} _ = Refl
> double_injective {n=Z} {m=(S _)} Refl impossible
> double_injective {n=(S _)} {m=Z} Refl impossible
> double_injective {n=(S n')} {m=(S m')} eq =
> let eqss = succInjective _ _ $ succInjective _ _ eq
> in rewrite double_injective {n=n'} {m=m'} eqss in Refl
\todo[inline]{Edit the rest of the section to use \idr{induction}?}
The way we _start_ this proof is a bit delicate: if we begin with
intros n. induction n.
all is well. But if we begin it with
intros n m. induction n.
we get stuck in the middle of the inductive case...
Theorem double_injective_FAILED : ∀n m,
double n = double m -> n = m.
Proof.
intros n m. induction n as [| n']. - (* n = Z *) simpl. intros eq. destruct m
as [| m'].
+ (* m = Z *) reflexivity. + (* m = S m' *) inversion eq.
- (* n = S n' *) intros eq. destruct m as [| m'].
+ (* m = Z *) inversion eq. + (* m = S m' *) apply f_equal.
At this point, the induction hypothesis, IHn', does not give us n' = m' -- there
is an extra S in the way -- so the goal is not provable.
Abort.
What went wrong?
The problem is that, at the point we invoke the induction hypothesis, we have
already introduced m into the context -- intuitively, we have told Coq, "Let's
consider some particular n and m..." and we now have to prove that, if double n
= double m for these particular n and m, then n = m.
The next tactic, induction n says to Coq: We are going to show the goal by
induction on n. That is, we are going to prove, for all n, that the proposition
- P n = "if double n = double m, then n = m"
holds, by showing
- P Z
(i.e., "if double Z = double m then Z = m") and
- P n -> P (S n)
(i.e., "if double n = double m then n = m" implies "if double (S n) = double
m then S n = m").
If we look closely at the second statement, it is saying something rather
strange: it says that, for a particular m, if we know
- "if double n = double m then n = m"
then we can prove
- "if double (S n) = double m then S n = m".
To see why this is strange, let's think of a particular m -- say, 5. The
statement is then saying that, if we know
- Q = "if double n = 10 then n = 5"
then we can prove
- R = "if double (S n) = 10 then S n = 5".
But knowing Q doesn't give us any help at all with proving R! (If we tried to
prove R from Q, we would start with something like "Suppose double (S n) =
10..." but then we'd be stuck: knowing that double (S n) is 10 tells us nothing
about whether double n is 10, so Q is useless.)
Trying to carry out this proof by induction on n when m is already in the
context doesn't work because we are then trying to prove a relation involving
every n but just a single m.
The successful proof of double_injective leaves m in the goal statement at the
point where the induction tactic is invoked on n:
Theorem double_injective : ∀n m,
double n = double m -> n = m.
Proof.
intros n. induction n as [| n']. - (* n = Z *) simpl. intros m eq. destruct m
as [| m'].
+ (* m = Z *) reflexivity. + (* m = S m' *) inversion eq.
- (* n = S n' *) simpl.
Notice that both the goal and the induction hypothesis are different this time:
the goal asks us to prove something more general (i.e., to prove the statement
for every m), but the IH is correspondingly more flexible, allowing us to choose
any m we like when we apply the IH.
intros m eq.
Now we've chosen a particular m and introduced the assumption that double n =
double m. Since we are doing a case analysis on n, we also need a case analysis
on m to keep the two "in sync."
destruct m as [| m']. + (* m = Z *) simpl.
The 0 case is trivial:
inversion eq.
+ (* m = S m' *)
apply f_equal.
At this point, since we are in the second branch of the destruct m, the m'
mentioned in the context is the predecessor of the m we started out talking
about. Since we are also in the S branch of the induction, this is perfect: if
we instantiate the generic m in the IH with the current m' (this instantiation
is performed automatically by the apply in the next step), then IHn' gives us
exactly what we need to finish the proof.
apply IHn'. inversion eq. reflexivity. Qed.
What you should take away from all this is that we need to be careful about
using induction to try to prove something too specific: To prove a property of n
and m by induction on n, it is sometimes important to leave m generic.
The following exercise requires the same pattern.
==== Exercise: 2 stars (beq_nat_true)
\ \todo[inline]{We explicitly write out implicits as having type \idr{Nat} since
\idr{(==)} is polymorphic}
> beq_nat_true : {n, m : Nat} -> n == m = True -> n = m
> beq_nat_true prf = ?beq_nat_true_rhs
$\square$
==== Exercise: 2 stars, advanced (beq_nat_true_informal)
Give a careful informal proof of \idr{beq_nat_true}, being as explicit as possible
about quantifiers.
> -- FILL IN HERE
$\square$
\todo[inline]{What to do with the rest of this?}
The strategy of doing fewer intros before an induction to obtain a more general
IH doesn't always work by itself; sometimes some rearrangement of quantified
variables is needed. Suppose, for example, that we wanted to prove
double_injective by induction on m instead of n.
Theorem double_injective_take2_FAILED : ∀n m,
double n = double m -> n = m.
Proof.
intros n m. induction m as [| m']. - (* m = Z *) simpl. intros eq. destruct n
as [| n'].
+ (* n = Z *) reflexivity. + (* n = S n' *) inversion eq.
- (* m = S m' *) intros eq. destruct n as [| n'].
+ (* n = Z *) inversion eq. + (* n = S n' *) apply f_equal.
(* Stuck again here, just like before. *)
Abort.
The problem is that, to do induction on m, we must first introduce n. (If we
simply say induction m without introducing anything first, Coq will
automatically introduce n for us!)
What can we do about this? One possibility is to rewrite the statement of the
lemma so that m is quantified before n. This works, but it's not nice: We don't
want to have to twist the statements of lemmas to fit the needs of a particular
strategy for proving them! Rather we want to state them in the clearest and most
natural way.
What we can do instead is to first introduce all the quantified variables and
then re-generalize one or more of them, selectively taking variables out of the
context and putting them back at the beginning of the goal. The generalize
dependent tactic does this.
Theorem double_injective_take2 : ∀n m,
double n = double m -> n = m.
Proof.
intros n m. (* n and m are both in the context *) generalize dependent n. (*
Now n is back in the goal and we can do induction on
m and get a sufficiently general IH. *)
induction m as [| m']. - (* m = Z *) simpl. intros n eq. destruct n as [| n'].
+ (* n = Z *) reflexivity. + (* n = S n' *) inversion eq.
- (* m = S m' *) intros n eq. destruct n as [| n'].
+ (* n = Z *) inversion eq. + (* n = S n' *) apply f_equal.
apply IHm'. inversion eq. reflexivity. Qed.
Let's look at an informal proof of this theorem. Note that the proposition we
prove by induction leaves n quantified, corresponding to the use of generalize
dependent in our formal proof.
_Theorem_: For any nats n and m, if double n = double m, then n = m.
_Proof_: Let m be a Nat. We prove by induction on m that, for any n, if double n
= double m then n = m.
- First, suppose m = 0, and suppose n is a number such that double n = double
m. We must show that n = 0.
Since m = 0, by the definition of double we have double n = 0. There are two
cases to consider for n. If n = 0 we are done, since m = 0 = n, as required.
Otherwise, if n = S n' for some n', we derive a contradiction: by the
definition of double, we can calculate double n = S (S (double n')), but
this contradicts the assumption that double n = 0.
- Second, suppose m = S m' and that n is again a number such that double n =
double m. We must show that n = S m', with the induction hypothesis that for
every number s, if double s = double m' then s = m'.
By the fact that m = S m' and the definition of double, we have double n = S
(S (double m')). There are two cases to consider for n.
If n = 0, then by definition double n = 0, a contradiction.
Thus, we may assume that n = S n' for some n', and again by the definition
of double we have S (S (double n')) = S (S (double m')), which implies by
inversion that double n' = double m'. Instantiating the induction hypothesis
with n' thus allows us to conclude that n' = m', and it follows immediately
that S n' = S m'. Since S n' = n and S m' = m, this is just what we wanted
to show. $\square$
Before we close this section and move on to some exercises, let's digress
briefly and use \idr{beq_nat_true} to prove a similar property of identifiers
that we'll need in later chapters:
> data Id : Type where
> MkId : Nat -> Id
> beq_id : (x1, x2 : Id) -> Bool
> beq_id (MkId n1) (MkId n2) = n1 == n2
> beq_id_true : beq_id x y = True -> x = y
> beq_id_true {x=MkId x'} {y=MkId y'} prf =
> rewrite beq_nat_true {n=x'} {m=y'} prf in Refl
=== Exercise: 3 stars, recommended (gen_dep_practice)
Prove this by induction on \idr{l}.
> data Option : (x : Type) -> Type where
> Some : x -> Option x
> None : Option x
> nth_error : (l : List x) -> (n : Nat) -> Option x
> nth_error [] n = None
> nth_error (a::l') n = if n == 0
> then Some a
> else nth_error l' (Nat.pred n)
> nth_error_after_last: (n : Nat) -> (l : List x) ->
> length l = n -> nth_error l n = None
$\square$
== Unfolding Definitions
\todo[inline]{Edit}
It sometimes happens that we need to manually unfold a definition so that we can
manipulate its right-hand side. For example, if we define...
> square : Nat -> Nat
> square n = n * n
... and try to prove a simple fact about square...
> square_mult : (n, m : Nat) -> square (n * m) = square n * square m
> square_mult n m = rewrite multAssociative (n*m) n m in
> rewrite multCommutative (n*m) n in
> rewrite multAssociative (n*n) m m in
> rewrite multAssociative n n m in Refl
... we succeed because Idris unfolds everything for us automatically.
\todo[inline]{Remove the next part?}
... we get stuck: simpl doesn't simplify anything at this point, and since we
haven't proved any other facts about square, there is nothing we can apply or
rewrite with.
To make progress, we can manually unfold the definition of square:
unfold square.
Now we have plenty to work with: both sides of the equality are expressions
involving multiplication, and we have lots of facts about multiplication at our
disposal. In particular, we know that it is commutative and associative, and
from these facts it is not hard to finish the proof.
rewrite mult_assoc. assert (H : n * m * n = n * n * m). { rewrite mult_comm.
apply mult_assoc. } rewrite H. rewrite mult_assoc. reflexivity.
Qed.
At this point, a deeper discussion of unfolding and simplification is in order.
You may already have observed that \idr{Refl} will often unfold the definitions
of functions automatically when this allows them to make progress. For example,
if we define \idr{foo m} to be the constant \idr{5}...
> foo : Nat -> Nat
> foo x = 5
then \idr{Refl} in the following proof will unfold \idr{foo m} to \idr{(\x => 5)
m} and then further simplify this expression to just \idr{5}.
> silly_fact_1 : foo m + 1 = foo (m + 1) + 1
> silly_fact_1 = Refl
However, this automatic unfolding is rather conservative. For example, if we
define a slightly more complicated function involving a pattern match...
> bar : Nat -> Nat
> bar Z = 5
> bar (S _) = 5
...then the analogous proof will get stuck:
```idris
silly_fact_2_FAILED : bar m + 1 = bar (m + 1) + 1
silly_fact_2_FAILED = Refl
```
The reason that \idr{Refl} doesn't make progress here is that it notices that,
after tentatively unfolding \idr{bar m}, it is left with a match whose
scrutinee, \idr{m}, is a variable, so the match cannot be simplified further.
(It is not smart enough to notice that the two branches of the match are
identical.) So it gives up on unfolding \idr{bar m} and leaves it alone.
Similarly, tentatively unfolding \idr{bar (m+1)} leaves a match whose scrutinee
is a function application (that, itself, cannot be simplified, even after
unfolding the definition of \idr{+}), so \idr{Refl} leaves it alone.
At this point, there are two ways to make progress. One is to match on implicit
parameter \idr{m} to break the proof into two cases, each focusing on a more
concrete choice of \idr{m} (\idr{Z} vs \idr{S _}). In each case, the match
inside of \idr{bar} can now make progress, and the proof is easy to complete.
> silly_fact_2 : bar m + 1 = bar (m + 1) + 1
> silly_fact_2 {m=Z} = Refl
> silly_fact_2 {m=(S _)} = Refl
\todo[inline]{Edit}
This approach works, but it depends on our recognizing that the match hidden
inside bar is what was preventing us from making progress. A more
straightforward way to make progress is to explicitly tell Idris to unfold bar.
\todo[inline]{Can we destruct in Elab script? Maybe with \idr{deriveElim}?}
Fact silly_fact_2' : ∀m, bar m + 1 = bar (m + 1) + 1. Proof.
intros m. unfold bar.
Now it is apparent that we are stuck on the match expressions on both sides of
the =, and we can use destruct to finish the proof without thinking too hard.
destruct m.
- reflexivity.
- reflexivity.
Qed.
== Using \idr{destruct} on Compound Expressions
\todo[inline]{Edit. Explain \idr{with}}
We have seen many examples where destruct is used to perform case analysis of
the value of some variable. But sometimes we need to reason by cases on the
result of some _expression_. We can also do this with destruct.
Here are some examples:
> sillyfun : Nat -> Bool
> sillyfun n = if n == 3
> then False
> else if n == 5
> then False
> else False
> sillyfun_false : (n : Nat) -> sillyfun n = False
> sillyfun_false n with (n == 3)
> sillyfun_false n | True = Refl
> sillyfun_false n | False with (n == 5)
> sillyfun_false n | False | True = Refl
> sillyfun_false n | False | False = Refl
After unfolding \idr{sillyfun} in the above proof, we find that we are stuck on
\idr{if (n == 3) then ... else ...}. But either \idr{n} is equal to \idr{3} or
it isn't, so we can use \idr{with (n == 3)} to let us reason about the two
cases.
\todo[inline]{Edit}
In general, the destruct tactic can be used to perform case analysis of the
results of arbitrary computations. If e is an expression whose type is some
inductively defined type T, then, for each constructor c of T, destruct e
generates a subgoal in which all occurrences of e (in the goal and in the
context) are replaced by c.
==== Exercise: 3 stars, optional (combine_split)
> combine_split : (l : List (x,y)) -> (l1 : List x) -> (l2 : List y) ->
> unzip l = (l1, l2) -> zip l1 l2 = l
> combine_split l l1 l2 prf = ?combine_split_rhs
$\square$
However, destructing compound expressions requires a bit of care, as
such destructs can sometimes erase information we need to complete a proof. For
example, suppose we define a function \idr{sillyfun1} like this:
> sillyfun1 : Nat -> Bool
> sillyfun1 n = if n == 3
> then True
> else if n == 5
> then True
> else False
Now suppose that we want to convince Idris of the (rather obvious) fact that
\idr{sillyfun1 n} yields \idr{True} only when \idr{n} is odd. By analogy with
the proofs we did with \idr{sillyfun} above, it is natural to start the proof
like this:
> sillyfun1_odd : (n : Nat) -> sillyfun1 n = True -> oddb n = True
> sillyfun1_odd n prf with (n == 3) proof eq3
> sillyfun1_odd n Refl | True =
> rewrite beq_nat_true (sym eq3) {n} {m=3} in Refl
> sillyfun1_odd n prf | False with (n == 5) proof eq5
> sillyfun1_odd n Refl | False | True =
> rewrite beq_nat_true (sym eq5) {n} {m=5} in Refl
> sillyfun1_odd n prf | False | False = absurd prf
\todo[inline]{Edit the following, since \idr{with} works fine here as well}
We get stuck at this point because the context does not contain enough
information to prove the goal! The problem is that the substitution performed by
destruct is too brutal -- it threw away every occurrence of n == 3, but we need
to keep some memory of this expression and how it was destructed, because we
need to be able to reason that, since n == 3 = True in this branch of the case
analysis, it must be that n = 3, from which it follows that n is odd.
What we would really like is to substitute away all existing occurences of n ==
3, but at the same time add an equation to the context that records which case
we are in. The eqn: qualifier allows us to introduce such an equation, giving it
a name that we choose.
Theorem sillyfun1_odd : ∀(n : Nat),
sillyfun1 n = True -> oddb n = True.
Proof.
intros n eq. unfold sillyfun1 in eq. destruct (beq_nat n 3) eqn:Heqe3.
(* Now
we have the same state as at the point where we got
stuck above, except that the context contains an extra equality assumption,
which is exactly what we need to make progress. *) - (* e3 = True *) apply
beq_nat_true in Heqe3. rewrite -> Heqe3. reflexivity. - (* e3 = False *) (*
When we come to the second equality test in the body
of the function we are reasoning about, we can use eqn: again in the
same way, allow us to finish the proof. *)
destruct (beq_nat n 5) eqn:Heqe5.
+ (* e5 = True *)
apply beq_nat_true in Heqe5. rewrite -> Heqe5. reflexivity.
+ (* e5 = False *) inversion eq. Qed.