forked from idris-hackers/software-foundations
-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 0
/
Copy pathProofObjects.lidr
596 lines (422 loc) · 19.8 KB
/
ProofObjects.lidr
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
= ProofObjects : The Curry-Howard Correspondence
> module ProofObjects
>
\say{\textit{Algorithms are the computational content of proofs.}}
-- Robert Harper
> import Logic
> import IndProp
>
We have seen that Idris has mechanisms both for _programming_, using inductive
data types like \idr{Nat} or \idr{List} and functions over these types, and for
_proving_ properties of these programs, using inductive propositions (like
\idr{Ev}), implication, universal quantification, and the like. So far, we have
mostly treated these mechanisms as if they were quite separate, and for many
purposes this is a good way to think. But we have also seen hints that Idris's
programming and proving facilities are closely related. For example, the keyword
\idr{data} is used to declare both data types and propositions, and \idr{->} is
used both to describe the type of functions on data and logical implication.
This is not just a syntactic accident! In fact, programs and proofs in Idris are
almost the same thing. In this chapter we will study how this works.
We have already seen the fundamental idea: provability in Idris is represented
by concrete _evidence_. When we construct the proof of a basic proposition, we
are actually building a tree of evidence, which can be thought of as a data
structure.
If the proposition is an implication like \idr{A -> B}, then its proof will be
an evidence _transformer_: a recipe for converting evidence for \idr{A} into
evidence for \idr{B}. So at a fundamental level, proofs are simply programs that
manipulate evidence.
Question: If evidence is data, what are propositions themselves?
Answer: They are types!
Look again at the formal definition of the \idr{Ev} property.
```idris
data Ev : Nat -> Type where
Ev_0 : Ev Z
Ev_SS : {n : Nat} -> Ev n -> Ev (S (S n))
```
Suppose we introduce an alternative pronunciation of "\idr{:}". Instead of "has
type," we can say "is a proof of." For example, the second line in the
definition of \idr{Ev} declares that \idr{Ev_0 : Ev 0}. Instead of "\idr{Ev_0}
has type \idr{Ev 0}," we can say that "\idr{Ev_0} is a proof of \idr{Ev 0}."
This pun between types and propositions — between \idr{:} as "has type" and
\idr{:} as "is a proof of" or "is evidence for" — is called the Curry-Howard
correspondence. It proposes a deep connection between the world of logic and the
world of computation:
propositions ~ types
proofs ~ data values
\todo[inline]{Add http://dl.acm.org/citation.cfm?id=2699407 as a link}
See [Wadler 2015] for a brief history and an up-to-date exposition.
Many useful insights follow from this connection. To begin with, it gives us a
natural interpretation of the type of the \idr{Ev_SS} constructor:
```idris
λΠ> :t Ev_SS
Ev_SS : Ev n -> Ev (S (S n))
```
This can be read "\idr{Ev_SS} is a constructor that takes two arguments — a
number \idr{n} and evidence for the proposition \idr{Ev n} — and yields evidence
for the proposition \idr{Ev (S (S n))}."
Now let's look again at a previous proof involving \idr{Ev}.
> ev_4 : Ev 4
> ev_4 = Ev_SS {n=2} $ Ev_SS {n=0} Ev_0
As with ordinary data values and functions, we can use the \idr{:printdef}
command to see the proof object that results from this proof script.
```idris
λΠ> :printdef ev_4
ev_4 : Ev 4
ev_4 = Ev_SS (Ev_SS Ev_0)
```
As a matter of fact, we can also write down this proof object directly, without
the need for a separate proof script:
```idris
λΠ> Ev_SS $ Ev_SS Ev_0
Ev_SS (Ev_SS Ev_0) : Ev 4
```
The expression \idr{Ev_SS {n=2} $ Ev_SS {n=0} Ev_0} can be thought of as
instantiating the parameterized constructor \idr{Ev_SS} with the specific
arguments \idr{2} and \idr{0} plus the corresponding proof objects for its
premises \idr{Ev 2} and \idr{Ev 0}. Alternatively, we can think of \idr{Ev_SS}
as a primitive "evidence constructor" that, when applied to a particular number,
wants to be further applied to evidence that that number is even; its type,
```idris
{n : Nat} -> Ev n -> Ev (S (S n))
```
expresses this functionality, in the same way that the polymorphic type
\idr{{x : Type} -> List x} expresses the fact that the constructor \idr{Nil} can
be thought of as a function from types to empty lists with elements of that
type.
\todo[inline]{Edit or remove}
We saw in the `Logic` chapter that we can use function application syntax to
instantiate universally quantified variables in lemmas, as well as to supply
evidence for assumptions that these lemmas impose. For instance:
```coq
Theorem ev_4': ev 4.
Proof.
apply (ev_SS 2 (ev_SS 0 ev_0)).
Qed.
```
We can now see that this feature is a trivial consequence of the status the
Idris grants to proofs and propositions: Lemmas and hypotheses can be combined
in expressions (i.e., proof objects) according to the same basic rules used for
programs in the language.
== Proof Scripts
\ \todo[inline]{Rewrite, keep explanation about holes? Seems a bit late for
that}
The _proof objects_ we've been discussing lie at the core of how Idris operates.
When Idris is following a proof script, what is happening internally is that it
is gradually constructing a proof object — a term whose type is the proposition
being proved. The expression on the right hand side of \idr{=} tell it how to
build up a term of the required type. To see this process in action, let's use
the `Show Proof` command to display the current state of the proof tree at
various points in the following tactic proof.
```coq
Theorem ev_4'' : ev 4.
Proof.
Show Proof.
apply ev_SS.
Show Proof.
apply ev_SS.
Show Proof.
apply ev_0.
Show Proof.
Qed.
```
At any given moment, Idris has constructed a term with a "hole" (indicated by
`?Goal` here, and so on), and it knows what type of evidence is needed to fill
this hole.
Each hole corresponds to a subgoal, and the proof is finished when there are no
more subgoals. At this point, the evidence we've built stored in the global
context under the name given in the type definition.
Tactic proofs are useful and convenient, but they are not essential: in
principle, we can always construct the required evidence by hand, as shown
above. Then we can use `Definition` (rather than `Theorem`) to give a global
name directly to a piece of evidence.
```coq
Definition ev_4''' : ev 4 :=
ev_SS 2 (ev_SS 0 ev_0).
```
All these different ways of building the proof lead to exactly the same evidence
being saved in the global environment.
```coq
Print ev_4.
(* ===> ev_4 = ev_SS 2 (ev_SS 0 ev_0) : ev 4 *)
Print ev_4'.
(* ===> ev_4' = ev_SS 2 (ev_SS 0 ev_0) : ev 4 *)
Print ev_4''.
(* ===> ev_4'' = ev_SS 2 (ev_SS 0 ev_0) : ev 4 *)
Print ev_4'''.
(* ===> ev_4''' = ev_SS 2 (ev_SS 0 ev_0) : ev 4 *)
```
==== Exercise: 1 star (eight_is_even)
\ \todo[inline]{Remove?}
Give a tactic proof and a proof object showing that \idr{Ev 8}.
> ev_8 : Ev 8
> ev_8 = ?ev_8_rhs
$\square$
==== Quantifiers, Implications, Functions
\ \todo[inline]{Edit the section}
In Idris's computational universe (where data structures and programs live),
there are two sorts of values with arrows in their types: _constructors_
introduced by \idr{data} definitions, and _functions_.
Similarly, in Idris's logical universe (where we carry out proofs), there are
two ways of giving evidence for an implication: constructors introduced by
\idr{data}-defined propositions, and... functions!
For example, consider this statement:
> ev_plus4 : Ev n -> Ev (4 + n)
> ev_plus4 x = Ev_SS $ Ev_SS x
What is the proof object corresponding to `ev_plus4`?
We're looking for an expression whose type is
\idr{{n: Nat} -> Ev n -> Ev (4 + n)} — that is, a function that takes two
arguments (one number and a piece of evidence) and returns a piece of evidence!
Here it is:
```coq
Definition ev_plus4' : forall n, ev n -> ev (4 + n) :=
fun (n : Nat) => fun (H : ev n) =>
ev_SS (S (S n)) (ev_SS n H).
```
Recall that \idr{\n => blah} means "the function that, given \idr{n}, yields
\idr{blah}," and that Idris treats \idr{4 + n} and \idr{S (S (S (S n)))} as
synonyms. Another equivalent way to write this definition is:
```coq
Definition ev_plus4'' (n : Nat) (H : ev n) : ev (4 + n) :=
ev_SS (S (S n)) (ev_SS n H).
Check ev_plus4''.
(* ===> ev_plus4'' : forall n : Nat, ev n -> ev (4 + n) *)
```
When we view the proposition being proved by \idr{ev_plus4} as a function type,
one aspect of it may seem a little unusual. The second argument's type,
\idr{Ev n}, mentions the _value_ of the first argument, \idr{n}. While such
_dependent types_ are not found in conventional programming languages, they can
be useful in programming too, as the recent flurry of activity in the functional
programming community demonstrates.
\todo[inline]{Reword?}
Notice that both implication (\idr{->}) and quantification
(\idr{(x : t) -> f x}) correspond to functions on evidence. In fact, they are
really the same thing: \idr{->} is just a shorthand for a degenerate use of
quantification where there is no dependency, i.e., no need to give a name to the
type on the left-hand side of the arrow.
For example, consider this proposition:
> ev_plus2 : Type
> ev_plus2 = (n : Nat) -> (e : Ev n) -> Ev (n + 2)
A proof term inhabiting this proposition would be a function with two arguments:
a number \idr{n} and some evidence \idr{e} that \idr{n} is even. But the name
\idr{e} for this evidence is not used in the rest of the statement of
\idr{ev_plus2}, so it's a bit silly to bother making up a name for it. We could
write it like this instead:
> ev_plus2' : Type
> ev_plus2' = (n : Nat) -> Ev n -> Ev (n + 2)
In general, "\idr{p -> q}" is just syntactic sugar for "\idr{(_ : p) -> q}".
== Programming with Tactics
\ \todo[inline]{Edit and move to an appendix about ElabReflection/Pruviloj?}
If we can build proofs by giving explicit terms rather than executing tactic
scripts, you may be wondering whether we can build _programs_ using _tactics_
rather than explicit terms. Naturally, the answer is yes!
```coq
Definition add1 : Nat -> Nat.
intro n.
Show Proof.
apply S.
Show Proof.
apply n. Defined.
Print add1.
(* ==>
add1 = fun n : Nat => S n
: Nat -> Nat
*)
Compute add1 2.
(* ==> 3 : Nat *)
```
Notice that we terminate the `Definition` with a `.` rather than with `:=`
followed by a term. This tells Idris to enter _proof scripting mode_ to build an
object of type \idr{Nat -> Nat}. Also, we terminate the proof with `Defined`
rather than `Qed`; this makes the definition _transparent_ so that it can be
used in computation like a normally-defined function. (`Qed`-defined objects are
opaque during computation.)
This feature is mainly useful for writing functions with dependent types, which
we won't explore much further in this book. But it does illustrate the
uniformity and orthogonality of the basic ideas in Idris.
== Logical Connectives as Inductive Types
Inductive definitions are powerful enough to express most of the connectives and
quantifiers we have seen so far. Indeed, only universal quantification (and thus
implication) is built into Idris; all the others are defined inductively. We'll
see these definitions in this section.
=== Conjunction
\ \todo[inline]{Edit}
To prove that \idr{(p,q)} holds, we must present evidence for both \idr{p} and
\idr{q}. Thus, it makes sense to define a proof object for \idr{(p,q)} as
consisting of a pair of two proofs: one for \idr{p} and another one for \idr{q}.
This leads to the following definition.
> data And : (p, q : Type) -> Type where
> Conj : p -> q -> And p q
Notice the similarity with the definition of the \idr{Prod} type, given in
chapter `Poly`; the only difference is that \idr{Prod} takes Type arguments,
whereas and takes Prop arguments.
```idris
data Prod : (x, y : Type) -> Type where
PPair : x -> y -> Prod x y
```
This should clarify why pattern matching can be used on a conjunctive
hypothesis. Case analysis allows us to consider all possible ways in which
\idr{(p,q)} was proved — here just one (the \idr{Conj} constructor). Similarly,
the `split` tactic actually works for any inductively defined proposition with
only one constructor. In particular, it works for \idr{And}:
> and_comm : (And p q) <-> (And q p)
> and_comm = (\(Conj x y) => Conj y x,
> \(Conj y x) => Conj x y)
This shows why the inductive definition of `and` can be manipulated by tactics
as we've been doing. We can also use it to build proofs directly, using
pattern-matching. For instance:
> and_comm'_aux : And p q -> And q p
> and_comm'_aux (Conj x y) = Conj y x
> and_comm' : (And p q) <-> (And q p)
> and_comm' {p} {q} = (and_comm'_aux {p} {q}, and_comm'_aux {p=q} {q=p})
==== Exercise: 2 stars, optional (conj_fact)
Construct a proof object demonstrating the following proposition.
> conj_fact : And p q -> And q r -> And p r
> conj_fact pq qr = ?conj_fact_rhs
$\square$
=== Disjunction
The inductive definition of disjunction uses two constructors, one for each side
of the disjunct:
> data Or : (p, q : Type) -> Type where
> IntroL : p -> Or p q
> IntroR : q -> Or p q
This declaration explains the behavior of pattern matching on a disjunctive
hypothesis, since the generated subgoals match the shape of the \idr{IntroL} and
\idr{IntroR} constructors.
Once again, we can also directly write proof objects for theorems involving
\idr{Or}, without resorting to tactics.
==== Exercise: 2 stars, optional (or_comm)
\ \todo[inline]{Edit}
Try to write down an explicit proof object for \idr{or_comm} (without using
`Print` to peek at the ones we already defined!).
> or_comm : Or p q -> Or q p
> or_comm pq = ?or_comm_rhs
$\square$
=== Existential Quantification
To give evidence for an existential quantifier, we package a witness \idr{x}
together with a proof that \idr{x} satisfies the property \idr{p}:
> data Ex : (p : a -> Type) -> Type where
> ExIntro : (x : a) -> p x -> Ex p
This may benefit from a little unpacking. The core definition is for a type
former \idr{Ex} that can be used to build propositions of the form \idr{Ex p},
where \idr{p} itself is a function from witness values in the type \idr{a} to
propositions. The \idr{ExIntro} constructor then offers a way of constructing
evidence for \idr{Ex p}, given a witness \idr{x} and a proof of \idr{p x}.
The more familiar form \idr{(x ** p x)} desugars to an expression involving
\idr{Ex}:
\todo[inline]{Edit}
```coq
Check ex (fun n => ev n).
(* ===> exists n : Nat, ev n
: Prop *)
```
Here's how to define an explicit proof object involving \idr{Ex}:
> some_nat_is_even : Ex (\n => Ev n)
> some_nat_is_even = ExIntro 4 (Ev_SS $ Ev_SS Ev_0)
==== Exercise: 2 stars, optional (ex_ev_Sn)
Complete the definition of the following proof object:
> ex_ev_Sn : Ex (\n => Ev (S n))
> ex_ev_Sn = ?ex_ev_Sn_rhs
$\square$
\subsection{\idr{Unit} and \idr{Void}}
The inductive definition of the \idr{Unit} proposition is simple:
```idris
data Unit : Type where
() : Unit
```
It has one constructor (so every proof of \idr{Unit} is the same, so being given
a proof of\idr{Unit} is not informative.)
\idr{Void} is equally simple — indeed, so simple it may look syntactically wrong
at first glance!
\todo[inline]{Edit, this actually is wrong, stdlib uses \idr{runElab} to define
it}
```idris
data Void : Type where
```
That is, \idr{Void} is an inductive type with _no_ constructors — i.e., no way
to build evidence for it.
== Equality
\ \todo[inline]{Edit, it actually is built in}
Even Idris's equality relation is not built in. It has the following inductive
definition. (Actually, the definition in the standard library is a small variant
of this, which gives an induction principle that is slightly easier to use.)
> data PropEq : {t : Type} -> t -> t -> Type where
> EqRefl : PropEq x x
> syntax [x] "='" [y] = PropEq x y
The way to think about this definition is that, given a set \idr{t}, it defines
a _family_ of propositions "\idr{x} is equal to \idr{y}," indexed by pairs of
values (\idr{x} and \idr{y}) from \idr{t}. There is just one way of constructing
evidence for each member of this family: applying the constructor \idr{EqRefl}
to a type \idr{t} and a value \idr{x : t} yields evidence that \idr{x} is equal
to \idr{x}.
\todo[inline]{Edit}
We can use \idr{EqRefl} to construct evidence that, for example, \idr{2 = 2}.
Can we also use it to construct evidence that \idr{1 + 1 = 2}? Yes, we can.
Indeed, it is the very same piece of evidence! The reason is that Idris treats
as "the same" any two terms that are _convertible_ according to a simple set of
computation rules. These rules, which are similar to those used by `Compute`,
include evaluation of function application, inlining of definitions, and
simplification of `match`es.
> four : (2 + 2) =' (1 + 3)
> four = EqRefl
The \idr{Refl} that we have used to prove equalities up to now is essentially
just an application of an equality constructor.
\todo[inline]{Edit}
In tactic-based proofs of equality, the conversion rules are normally hidden in
uses of `simpl` (either explicit or implicit in other tactics such as
`reflexivity`). But you can see them directly at work in the following explicit
proof objects:
```coq
Definition four' : 2 + 2 = 1 + 3 :=
eq_refl 4.
```
> singleton : ([]++[x]) =' (x::[])
> singleton = EqRefl
> quiz6 : Ex (\x => (x + 3) =' 4)
> quiz6 = ExIntro 1 EqRefl
==== Exercise: 2 stars (equality__leibniz_equality)
The inductive definition of equality corresponds to _Leibniz equality_: what we
mean when we say "\idr{x} and \idr{y} are equal" is that every property \idr{p}
that is true of \idr{x} is also true of \idr{y}.
> equality__leibniz_equality : (x =' y) -> ((p : t -> Type) -> p x -> p y)
> equality__leibniz_equality eq p px = ?equality__leibniz_equality_rhs
$\square$
==== Exercise: 5 stars, optional (leibniz_equality__equality)
Show that, in fact, the inductive definition of equality is _equivalent_ to
Leibniz equality:
> leibniz_equality__equality : ((p : t -> Type) -> p x -> p y) -> (x =' y)
> leibniz_equality__equality pxy = ?leibniz_equality__equality_rhs
$\square$
=== Inversion, Again
\ \todo[inline]{Edit/remove}
We've seen `inversion` used with both equality hypotheses and hypotheses about
inductively defined propositions. Now that we've seen that these are actually
the same thing, we're in a position to take a closer look at how `inversion`
behaves.
In general, the `inversion` tactic...
- takes a hypothesis `H` whose type `P` is inductively defined, and
- for each constructor `C` in `P`'s definition,
- generates a new subgoal in which we assume `H` was built with `C`,
- adds the arguments (premises) of `C` to the context of the subgoal as
extra hypotheses,
- matches the conclusion (result type) of `C` against the current goal and
calculates a set of equalities that must hold in order for `C` to be
applicable,
- adds these equalities to the context (and, for convenience, rewrites them
in the goal), and
- if the equalities are not satisfiable (e.g., they involve things like
\idr{S n = Z}), immediately solves the subgoal.
_Example_: If we invert a hypothesis built with \idr{Or}, there are two
constructors, so two subgoals get generated. The conclusion (result type) of the
constructor (\idr{Or p q}) doesn't place any restrictions on the form of \idr{p}
or \idr{q}, so we don't get any extra equalities in the context of the subgoal.
_Example_: If we invert a hypothesis built with \idr{And}, there is only one
constructor, so only one subgoal gets generated. Again, the conclusion (result
type) of the constructor (\idr{And p q}) doesn't place any restrictions on the
form of \idr{p} or \idr{q}, so we don't get any extra equalities in the context
of the subgoal. The constructor does have two arguments, though, and these can
be seen in the context in the subgoal.
_Example_: If we invert a hypothesis built with \idr{PropEq}, there is again
only one constructor, so only one subgoal gets generated. Now, though, the form
of the \idr{EqRefl} constructor does give us some extra information: it tells us
that the two arguments to \idr{PropEq} must be the same! The `inversion` tactic
adds this fact to the context.