-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 3
/
paper-generic-freeness.tex
436 lines (363 loc) · 20.8 KB
/
paper-generic-freeness.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
\documentclass[oneside]{amsart}
\usepackage[utf8]{inputenc}
\usepackage{amsthm,mathtools,tikz,float,caption}
\usetikzlibrary{patterns,matrix}
\usepackage[protrusion=true]{microtype}
\usepackage{breakurl}
\usepackage{hyperref}
\usepackage[natbib=true,style=numeric,maxnames=10]{biblatex}
\usepackage[babel]{csquotes}
\bibliography{paper-generic-freeness.bib}
\title[Grothendieck's generic freeness lemma]{An elementary and constructive
proof of Grothendieck's generic freeness lemma}
\author{Ingo Blechschmidt}
\address{Max Planck Institute for Mathematics in the Sciences \\
Inselstraße 22 \\
04103 Leipzig, Germany}
\email{ingo.blechschmidt@mis.mpg.de}
\theoremstyle{definition}
\newtheorem{defn}{Definition}[]
\newtheorem{ex}[defn]{Example}
\theoremstyle{plain}
\newtheorem{prop}[defn]{Proposition}
\newtheorem{cor}[defn]{Corollary}
\newtheorem{lemma}[defn]{Lemma}
\newtheorem{thm}[defn]{Theorem}
\newtheorem{scholium}[defn]{Scholium}
\theoremstyle{remark}
\newtheorem{rem}[defn]{Remark}
\newtheorem{question}[defn]{Question}
\newtheorem{speculation}[defn]{Speculation}
\newtheorem{caveat}[defn]{Caveat}
\newtheorem{conjecture}[defn]{Conjecture}
\newcommand{\XXX}[1]{\textbf{XXX: #1}}
\newcommand{\aaa}{\mathfrak{a}}
\newcommand{\bbb}{\mathfrak{b}}
\newcommand{\mmm}{\mathfrak{m}}
\newcommand{\I}{\mathcal{I}}
\newcommand{\J}{\mathcal{J}}
\newcommand{\E}{\mathcal{E}}
\newcommand{\B}{\mathcal{B}}
\renewcommand{\O}{\mathcal{O}}
\newcommand{\defeq}{\vcentcolon=}
\DeclareMathOperator{\Spec}{Spec}
\newcommand{\stacksproject}[1]{\cite[{\href{https://stacks.math.columbia.edu/tag/#1}{Tag~#1}}]{stacks-project}}
\begin{document}
\begin{abstract}
We present a new and direct proof of Grothendieck's generic freeness
lemma in its general form. Unlike the previously published proofs, it does not
proceed in a series of reduction steps and is fully constructive, not
using the axiom of choice or even the law of excluded middle. It was
found by unwinding the result of a general topos-theoretic technique.
\end{abstract}
\maketitle
\thispagestyle{empty}
\noindent
We prove Grothendieck's generic freeness lemma in the
following form.
\begin{thm}\label{thm:algebraic}Let~$A$ be a reduced ring (commutative, with unit). Let~$B$ be
an~$A$-algebra of finite type. Let~$M$ be a finitely generated~$B$-module.
If~$f = 0$ is the only element of~$A$ such that
\begin{enumerate}
\item the~$A[f^{-1}]$-modules $B[f^{-1}]$ and $M[f^{-1}]$ are free,
\item the~$A[f^{-1}]$-algebra~$B[f^{-1}]$ is of finite presentation and
\item the~$B[f^{-1}]$-module~$M[f^{-1}]$ is finitely presented,
\end{enumerate}
then~$1 = 0$ in~$A$.
\end{thm}
Previously known proofs either only cover the case where~$A$ is a Noetherian
integral domain, where one can argue by \emph{dévissage} (see for
instance~\cite[Lemme~6.9.2]{ega-4-2},
\cite[Thm.~24.1]{matsumura:commutative-ring-theory} or
\cite[Thm.~14.4]{eisenbud:commutative-algebra}), or proceed in a series of
intermediate steps, reducing to that case (see for
instance~\cite{staats:generic-freeness} or~\stacksproject{051Q}); but in fact,
a direct proof is possible and shorter. The new proof unveils a certain
combinatorial aspect to Grothendieck's generic freeness lemma, does not require
any advanced prerequisites in commutative algebra and does not use the axiom of
choice or the law of excluded middle. It is purely element-based, not referring
to ideals of~$A$, and doesn't use Noether normalization.
Grothendieck's generic freeness lemma is often presented in contrapositive form
or in the following geometric variant:
\begin{thm}\label{thm:geometric}Let~$A$ be a reduced ring. Let~$B$ be
an~$A$-algebra of finite type. Let~$M$ be a finitely generated~$B$-module. Then
the space~$\Spec(A)$ contains a dense open~$U$ such that over~$U$,
\begin{enumerate}
\item[(a)] $B^\sim$ and~$M^\sim$ are locally free as sheaves of~$A^\sim$-modules,
\item[(b)] $B^\sim$ is of finite presentation as a sheaf of~$A^\sim$-algebras and
\item[(c)] $M^\sim$ is finitely presented as a sheaf of~$B^\sim$-modules.
\end{enumerate}
\end{thm}
Theorem~\ref{thm:geometric} immediately follows from
Theorem~\ref{thm:algebraic} by defining~$U$ as the union of all those basic
opens~$D(f)$ such that~(1),~(2) and~(3) hold. It is clear that~(a),~(b)
and~(c) hold over~$U$, and~$U$ is dense for if~$V$ is an arbitrary open
such that~$U \cap V = \emptyset$, the open~$V$ is itself empty: Let~$h \in A$ be
such that~$D(h) \subseteq V$. The hypothesis implies the assumptions of
Theorem~\ref{thm:algebraic} for the datum~$(A[h^{-1}], B[h^{-1}], M[h^{-1}])$.
Thus~$1 = 0 \in A[h^{-1}]$, so~$h$ is nilpotent and~$D(h) = \emptyset$.
The new proof was found using a general topos-theoretic technique which we
believe to be useful in other situations as well. This technique allows to view
reduced rings and their modules from a different point of view, one from which
reduced rings look like fields. Since Grothendieck's generic freeness
is trivial for fields, this technique yields a trivial proof for reduced rings.
The proof presented here was obtained by unwinding the topos-theoretic proof,
yielding a self-contained argument without any references to topos theory.
We refer readers who want to learn about this technique to a forthcoming companion
paper~\cite{blechschmidt:wlog}.
\textbf{Acknowledgments.} The proof presented here was prompted by a question by
user~HeinrichD on MathOverflow~\cite{mo:kernel} and greatly
benefited from discussions with Martin Brandenburg, who employed the constructive
version in a paper of his~\cite{brandenburg:schur}. We are grateful to Thierry
Coquand and Peter Schuster for valuable advice, to Giuseppe Rosolini and to
Yakov Varshavsky for
comments improving the presentation of the paper, and to Marc
Nieper-Wißkirchen for carefully guiding our PhD studies~\cite{blechschmidt:phd} at the University of
Augsburg, where most of the work for this paper was carried out.
\section{The proof of the finitely-generated case}
The following proposition is just a special instance of Grothendieck's generic
freeness lemma. Its proof is easier and shorter than the proof of the general
case, which is why we present it here. The general proof
will not refer to this one.
\begin{prop}Let~$A$ be a reduced ring. Let~$M$ be a finitely
generated~$A$-module. If~$f = 0$ is the only element of~$A$ such
that~$M[f^{-1}]$ is a finite free~$A[f^{-1}]$-module, then~$1 = 0$ in~$A$.
\end{prop}
\begin{proof}We proceed by induction on the length of a given generating family
of~$M$. Let~$M$ be generated by~$(v_1,\ldots,v_m)$.
We show that the family~$(v_1,\ldots,v_m)$ is linearly independent. Let~$\sum_i
a_i v_i = 0$. Over~$A[a_i^{-1}]$, the vector~$v_i \in M[a_i^{-1}]$ is a linear
combination of the other generators. Thus~$M[a_i^{-1}]$ can be generated as
an~$A[a_i^{-1}]$-module by fewer than~$m$ generators. The induction hypothesis,
applied to this module over~$A[a_i^{-1}]$, yields that~$1 = 0$ in~$A[a_i^{-1}]$. Since~$A$ is
reduced, this amounts to~$a_i = 0$.
We finish by using the assumption for~$f = 1$.
\end{proof}
We remark that the proof takes a somewhat curious course: Our goal is to
verify~$1 = 0$, but as an intermediate step we verify that~$M$ is free, which
after the fact will be a trivial statement. The general proof in the next
section will have a similar style. This approach is reminiscient of
Richman's uses of trivial rings~\cite{richman:trivial-rings}.
\section{The proof of the general case}
\begin{proof}[Proof of Theorem~\ref{thm:algebraic}]
Let~$B$ be generated by~$(x_1,\ldots,x_n)$ as an~$A$-algebra and
let~$M$ be generated by~$(v_1,\ldots,v_m)$ as a~$B$-module. We endow the sets
\begin{align*}
\I &\defeq \{ (i_1,\ldots,i_n) \,|\, i_1,\ldots,i_n \geq 0 \}
\quad\text{and} \\
\J &\defeq \{ (\ell, i_1,\ldots,i_n) \,|\, 1 \leq \ell \leq m, i_1,\ldots,i_n \geq 0 \}
\end{align*}
with the lexicographic order. The family~$(w_J)_{J \in \J} \defeq (x_1^{i_1}
\cdots x_n^{i_n} v_\ell)_{(\ell,i_1,\ldots,i_n) \in \J}$ generates~$M$ as
an~$A$-module, and we will call a subfamily~$(w_J)_{J \in \J' \subseteq \J}$
\emph{good} if and only if for all~$J \in \J$, the vector~$w_J$ is a linear
combination of the vectors~$(w_{J'})_{J' \in \J', J' \preceq J}$,
and if~$(\ell,i_1,\ldots,i_n) \not\in \J'$ implies~$(\ell,k_1,\ldots,k_n) \not\in
\J'$ for all~$k_1 \geq i_1, \ldots, k_n \geq i_n$. Figure~\ref{fig:good} shows
how a good generating family can look like.
Similarly, we define when a subfamily of the canonical generating
family~$(x_1^{i_1} \cdots x_n^{i_n})_{(i_1,\ldots,i_n) \in \I}$ of~$B$ is good
(which is just the special case~$m = 1$).
We then proceed by induction on the
shapes of a given good generating family~$(w_J)_{J \in \J'}$ for~$M$ and a given
good generating family~$(s_I)_{I \in \I'}$ for~$B$, starting with the canonical ones. It is
reasonably obvious that this induction is well-founded; the formal statement
that it is so is known as \emph{Dickson's Lemma} (see, for
instance,~\cite[Thm.~1.1]{veldman:kruskal}).
We show that~$(w_J)_{J \in \J'}$ is a basis of~$M$ by verifying linear
independence. Thus let~$\sum_J a_J w_J = 0$ in~$M$. We show that all
coefficients in this sum are zero, starting with the largest
appearing index~$J$: In the module~$M[a_J^{-1}]$ over the localized ring~$A[a_J^{-1}]$,
the vector~$w_J$ is a linear combination of generators with
smaller index. Removing~$w_J = x_1^{i_1} \cdots x_n^{i_n} v_\ell$ and also all
vectors~$x_1^{k_1} \cdots x_n^{k_n} v_\ell$ where~$k_1 \geq i_1, \ldots,
k_n \geq i_n$, we obtain a subfamily which is still good for
the localized module. The induction hypothesis, applied
to~$A[a_J^{-1}]$ and its module~$M[a_J^{-1}]$, therefore implies that $A[a_J^{-1}] = 0$.
Thus $a_J = 0$ since~$A$ is reduced.
Similarly, we show that the given good generating family~$(s_I)_{I \in \I'}$ is
a basis. Thus~$M$ and~$B$ are free over~$A$. We fix for any corner~$J$
of~$\J'$, as indicated in Figure~\ref{fig:good},
a way of expressing~$w_J = \sum_K a_{JK} w_K$ as a linear combination of
generators with strictly smaller index. Let~$\widehat w_{(\ell,i_1,\ldots,i_n)}
\defeq x_1^{i_1} \cdots x_n^{i_n} V_\ell$ in the free~$B$-module~$B\langle
V_1,\ldots, V_m\rangle$. The canonical map
\[ \widehat M \defeq B\langle V_1,\ldots, V_m\rangle/
(\widehat w_J - \textstyle\sum_K a_{JK} \widehat w_K)_{\text{$J$ corner of~$\J'$}} \longrightarrow M
\]
is trivially well-defined and surjective. It is also injective, since any
element of~$\widehat M$ can be written as an~$A$-linear combination of the
vectors~$(\widehat w_J)_{J \in \J'}$ by employing the corner relations a finite
number of times. Therefore~$M$ is finitely presented as a~$B$-module.
In a similar vein, a quotient algebra of~$A[X_1,\ldots,X_n]$, where
we mod out by a suitable ideal with as many generators as corners of~$\I'$, is
isomorphic to~$B$. Thus~$B$ is finitely presented as an~$A$-algebra.
We finish by using the assumption for~$f = 1$.
\end{proof}
\begin{figure}[t]
\captionsetup{width=.9\linewidth}
\begin{tikzpicture}[scale=0.9]
\draw[step=1cm,gray,very thin] (0,0) grid (8,8);
\draw
(0,8) -- (0,0) -- (8,0);
\fill[pattern=north east lines,pattern color=gray,opacity=0.5]
(2,8) -- (2,5) -- (5,5) -- (5,3) -- (6,3) -- (6,2) -- (8,2) -- (8,8);
\draw
(2,8) -- (2,5) -- (5,5) -- (5,3) -- (6,3) -- (6,2) -- (8,2);
\fill[fill=black] (2,5.25) -- (2,5) -- (2.25,5) -- (2.25,5.25);
\fill[fill=black] (5,3.25) -- (5,3) -- (5.25,3) -- (5.25,3.25);
\fill[fill=black] (6,2.25) -- (6,2) -- (6.25,2) -- (6.25,2.25);
\fill[fill=blue!40!white,opacity=0.5]
(0,8) -- (0,0) -- (4,0) -- (4,3) -- (3,3) -- (3,5) -- (2,5) -- (2,8);
\fill[fill=red!40!white,opacity=0.5]
(3,3) -- (4,3) -- (4,4) -- (3,4);
% !perl -we 'for my $y (reverse 0..7) { for my $x (0..7) { print % "\$x^$x\Ey^$y\$ & " } print "\\\\ \n" }'
\begin{scope}[yshift=4cm, xshift=4cm]
\matrix[matrix of nodes,nodes={inner sep=0pt,text width=0.9cm,align=center,minimum height=0.9cm}]{
\tiny $x^0y^7v_1$ & \tiny $x^1y^7v_1$ & \tiny $x^2y^7v_1$ & \tiny $x^3y^7v_1$ & \tiny $x^4y^7v_1$ & \tiny $x^5y^7v_1$ & \tiny $x^6y^7v_1$ & \tiny $x^7y^7v_1$ & \\
\tiny $x^0y^6v_1$ & \tiny $x^1y^6v_1$ & \tiny $x^2y^6v_1$ & \tiny $x^3y^6v_1$ & \tiny $x^4y^6v_1$ & \tiny $x^5y^6v_1$ & \tiny $x^6y^6v_1$ & \tiny $x^7y^6v_1$ & \\
\tiny $x^0y^5v_1$ & \tiny $x^1y^5v_1$ & \tiny $x^2y^5v_1$ & \tiny $x^3y^5v_1$ & \tiny $x^4y^5v_1$ & \tiny $x^5y^5v_1$ & \tiny $x^6y^5v_1$ & \tiny $x^7y^5v_1$ & \\
\tiny $x^0y^4v_1$ & \tiny $x^1y^4v_1$ & \tiny $x^2y^4v_1$ & \tiny $x^3y^4v_1$ & \tiny $x^4y^4v_1$ & \tiny $x^5y^4v_1$ & \tiny $x^6y^4v_1$ & \tiny $x^7y^4v_1$ & \\
\tiny $x^0y^3v_1$ & \tiny $x^1y^3v_1$ & \tiny $x^2y^3v_1$ & \tiny $x^3y^3v_1$ & \tiny $x^4y^3v_1$ & \tiny $x^5y^3v_1$ & \tiny $x^6y^3v_1$ & \tiny $x^7y^3v_1$ & \\
\tiny $x^0y^2v_1$ & \tiny $x^1y^2v_1$ & \tiny $x^2y^2v_1$ & \tiny $x^3y^2v_1$ & \tiny $x^4y^2v_1$ & \tiny $x^5y^2v_1$ & \tiny $x^6y^2v_1$ & \tiny $x^7y^2v_1$ & \\
\tiny $x^0y^1v_1$ & \tiny $x^1y^1v_1$ & \tiny $x^2y^1v_1$ & \tiny $x^3y^1v_1$ & \tiny $x^4y^1v_1$ & \tiny $x^5y^1v_1$ & \tiny $x^6y^1v_1$ & \tiny $x^7y^1v_1$ & \\
\tiny $x^0y^0v_1$ & \tiny $x^1y^0v_1$ & \tiny $x^2y^0v_1$ & \tiny $x^3y^0v_1$ & \tiny $x^4y^0v_1$ & \tiny $x^5y^0v_1$ & \tiny $x^6y^0v_1$ & \tiny $x^7y^0v_1$ & \\
};
\end{scope}
\end{tikzpicture}
\caption{\label{fig:good}A graphical depiction of a good generating family (the non-hatched cells) in
the special case~$n = 2, m = 1$, writing~``$x$'' and~``$y$'' for~$x_1$ and~$x_2$. The hatched cells indicate vectors which
have already been removed from the family. The small black squares indicate
\emph{corners}. If the vector in the red cell will be found to be expressible
as a linear combination of vectors with smaller index (blue cells), it will
be removed, along with the vectors in all cells to the top and to the right
of the red cell.}
\end{figure}
\section{Conclusion}
Commutative algebra abounds with techniques which allow us to reduce quite
general situations to easier ones. These techniques often yield short and slick
proofs; however, they come at an expense: They are typically nonconstructive in
nature, employing for instance the axiom of choice, and do not argue using only
the data at hand, but using additional auxiliary objects such as maximal
ideals. We feel that once a subject is better understood, it is desirable to
have more informative, direct proofs available which illuminate the
proven claims more clearly; similar as to how bijective proofs are preferred over
calculational inductive ones in combinatorics.
Let us consider as a specific example the statement that the existence of a linear
surjection~$A^n \to A^m$ with~$n < m$ between finite free modules over an
arbitrary ring~$A$ implies~$1 = 0 \in A$. The standard proof of this fact proceeds
by contradiction and passes to the quotient~$A/\mmm$, where~$\mmm$ is a maximal
ideal of~$A$, thereby reducing to the situation that the ring is a field. In
contrast, a direct proof such as Richman's~\cite{richman:trivial-rings}
refers only to objects mentioned in the statement itself and
explicitly tells us how to deduce the equation~$1 = 0$ from the~$m$ equations
which express that each basis vector of~$A^m$ has a preimage.
In a similar fashion, the new proof of Grothendieck's generic freeness lemma
explicitly tells us how to deduce~$1 = 0$ from the given conditional
equations expressing that~$f = 0$ is the only element with properties~(1),~(2)
and~(3).
Direct proofs sometimes generalize to new situations where the reduction techniques
employed by more abstract proofs cannot be applied. This is the case for
Grothendieck's generic freeness lemma, which allows for the following
generalization:
\begin{thm}\label{thm:general-generic-freeness}
Let~$(X,\O_X)$ be a ringed space (or ringed locale, or ringed topos), such
that for every local section~$s$ of~$\O_X$, if the only open on which~$s$ is
invertible is the empty one, then~$s = 0$. Let~$\B$ be a sheaf
of~$\O_X$-algebras of finite type. Let~$\E$ be a sheaf of~$\B$-modules of finite type. Then there is a dense
open~$U$ such that over~$U$,
\begin{enumerate}
\item[(a)] $\B$ and~$\E$ are locally free as sheaves of~$\O_X$-modules,
\item[(b)] $\B$ is of finite presentation as a sheaf of~$\O_X$-algebras and
\item[(c)] $\E$ is finitely presented as a sheaf of~$\B$-modules.
\end{enumerate}
\end{thm}
% XXX: Check formulation of the topos case. Is it true that the join of open
% subtoposes is open?
\begin{proof}Our proof of Theorem~\ref{thm:algebraic} can be easily adapted to
this more general setting. Where that proof concludes~$a_J = 0$ for ring
elements~$a_J$ by considering the localized situation~$A[a_J^{-1}]$, we now
conclude~$a_J = 0$ for local sections~$a_J$ of~$\O_X$ by considering the
situation over the restriction to~$D(a_J)$. Whereas before this type of argument was
powered by the reducedness assumption on~$A$, it is now supported by the
assumption on~$X$.
We omit further details.
\end{proof}
The spectrum of a ring~$A$ is a space of the kind required by
Theorem~\ref{thm:general-generic-freeness} if and only if~$A$ is reduced,
thus Theorem~\ref{thm:general-generic-freeness} indeed
generalizes Theorem~\ref{thm:geometric}. Further examples for admissible spaces
are given by any topological, smooth or complex manifold; a corollary
of Theorem~\ref{thm:general-generic-freeness} for these examples is that
quotients of vector bundles, computed in the category of sheaves of modules,
are again vector bundles after restricting to suitable dense opens.
It is hard to say with certainty that a given proof does not generalize to a
new situation; but we do not see how this could be the case for the proofs
cited in the introduction.
\printbibliography
\end{document}
Recall that a module is Noetherian if and only if all of its submodules are
finitely generated. We call a module~$M$ over an~$A$-algebra~$B$ \emph{weakly
Noetherian} (over~$A$) if and only if, for all~$B$-submodules~$U \subseteq M$
and all~$f \in A$ the condition
\begin{multline*}
\text{for all~$g \in A$, if $U[(fg)^{-1}]$ is finitely generated as
an~$B[(fg)^{-1}]$-module,} \\
\text{then~$fg$ is nilpotent in~$A$} \end{multline*}
implies that~$f$ is nilpotent. Geometrically, this expresses that all
quasicoherent sheaves of submodules of~$M^\sim$ are, over a dense open
of~$\Spec(A)$, of finite type over~$B^\sim$. An~$A$-algebra~$B$
is \emph{weakly Noetherian} if and only if it is weakly Noetherian as a module
over itself.
This notion is interesting for the following reason.
\begin{lemma}\label{lemma:self-noetherian}
Let~$A$ be a reduced ring. Then~$A$, regarded as an algebra over itself, is
weakly Noetherian.\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}Let~$\aaa \subseteq A$ be an ideal. Let~$f \in A$ such that, for
any~$g \in A$, if~$\aaa[(fg)^{-1}]$ is finitely generated, then~$fg = 0$.
We verify that~$f = 0$.
We first show that~$\aaa[f^{-1}] = (0)$. Let~$g \in \aaa$. Then~$\aaa[(fg)^{-1}] =
(1)$ is finitely generated. Thus~$fg = 0$, hence~$g = 0$ in~$A[f^{-1}]$.
Since~$\aaa[f^{-1}]$ is finitely generated, we finish by using the
assumption for~$g = 1$.
\end{proof}
The weak Noetherian condition enjoys the same basic stability properties as the
usual Noetherian condition:
\begin{lemma}\label{lemma:noetherian-stability}
Let~$A$ be a ring. Let~$B$ be an~$A$-algebra.
\begin{enumerate}
\item If~$B$ is weakly Noetherian, then so is~$B[X]$.
\item Let~$0 \to M' \to M \to M'' \to 0$ be a short exact sequence
of~$B$-modules. Then~$M$ is weakly Noetherian if and only if~$M'$ and~$M''$
are.
\end{enumerate}
\end{lemma}
We can use these observations to finish the proof of Grothendieck's generic
freeness lemma.
\begin{prop}Let~$A$ be a reduced ring. Let~$B$ be an~$A$-algebra of finite type.
If~$f = 0$ is the only element of~$A$ such that~$B[f^{-1}]$ is of finite
presentation as an~$A[f^{-1}]$-algebra, then~$1 = 0$ in~$A$.
\end{prop}
\begin{proof}We write~$B = A[X_1,\ldots,X_n]/\aaa$. By Lemma~\ref{lemma:self-noetherian} and
Lemma~\ref{lemma:noetherian-stability}, the~$A$-algebra~$A[X_1,\ldots,X_n]$ is
weakly Noetherian. We can therefore conclude if we can show, for any~$g \in A$,
that if the ideal~$\aaa[g^{-1}]$ is finitely generated, then~$g = 0$. This
follows immediately from the assumption (for~$f = g$).
\end{proof}
\begin{prop}Let~$A$ be a reduced ring. Let~$B$ be an~$A$-algebra of finite type.
Let~$M$ be a finitely generated~$B$-module. If~$f = 0$ is the only element
of~$A$ such that~$M[f^{-1}]$ is finitely presented as an~$B[f^{-1}]$-module,
then~$1 = 0$ in~$A$.
\end{prop}
\begin{proof}We write~$M = B^n/U$ for an~$B$-submodule~$U$. By Lemma~\ref{lemma:self-noetherian} and
Lemma~\ref{lemma:noetherian-stability}, the~$B$-module~$B^n$ is weakly
Noetherian. We can therefore conclude if we can show, for any~$g \in A$, that if
the submodule~$U[g^{-1}]$ is finitely generated, then~$g = 0$. This follows
immediately from the assumption (for~$f = g$).
\end{proof}
\end{document}
TODO:
look into Perdry, Journal of Symbolic Computation for a pointer to the
Gordan--Dickson lemma. This might be cited.
TODO:
Cite Martin Brandenburg?